Guest post by Fabiana Alceste.
“You have the right to remain silent. Anything you say can and will be used against you in a court of law. You have the right to an attorney. If you cannot afford an attorney, one will be provided for you.” These words have likely been burned into our collective consciousness by the ubiquitous and fantastic TV series Law & Order (in my case, Law & Order: SVU). These words are often spoken as Olivia Benson and Elliot Stabler handcuff the main suspect of the episode—the last words trail off as they walk offscreen and the show cuts to a commercial break. We know this scene, and we know the words…but why do these warnings exist and for whom are they intended?
“You have the right to remain silent. Anything you say can and will be used against you in a court of law. You have the right to an attorney. If you cannot afford an attorney, one will be provided for you.” These words have likely been burned into our collective consciousness by the ubiquitous and fantastic TV series Law & Order (in my case, Law & Order: SVU). These words are often spoken as Olivia Benson and Elliot Stabler handcuff the main suspect of the episode—the last words trail off as they walk offscreen and the show cuts to a commercial break. We know this scene, and we know the words…but why do these warnings exist and for whom are they intended?
Benson and Stabler are ready to make the arrest! But first they need to inform the suspect of their Miranda Rights |
Custody is most easily identified
when it comes after formal arrest, like in Law & Order2. Anyone who
is arrested is necessarily in the custody of the police and thus requires legal
protections. But police often question individuals about crimes without
arresting them—how, then, do we know if they are in custody? The
court must determine whether, in the absence of arrest, there was a restriction
of the subject’s freedom of movement that is on par with formal arrest3.
(California v. Beheler 1983): first
by evaluating the objective circumstances of the questioning, and then by
asking whether a reasonable person in the suspect’s position would have felt
free to leave.
Objective circumstances
Courts
must weigh how the objective factors of the questioning contribute to a state
of custody. For instance, courts may consider: whether police informed the
suspect that he or she was free to leave or not under arrest; whether the
suspect agreed to be questioned voluntarily or initiated contact with the
police; whether police employed deceptive or coercive interrogation techniques
during the questioning; and whether the atmosphere of the questioning was under
police control4. Usually, the presence of the first two factors tend
to indicate that the subject was free to leave the questioning (and thus did
not require protections), whereas the last two suggest the suspect was in
custody5 (United States v.
Brown, 1993).
To
illustrate, imagine that a suspect arrives at the police station voluntarily,
is told that he is not under arrest, is questioned for only 20 minutes, and is
permitted to leave the station. A court would almost certainly label this
interview as noncustodial3, 6, 7. Although custody is not determined
by any single factor, but rather by the combination of all factors, courts
almost always find that questioning is noncustodial when police advise suspects
that they are free to leave3, 6 (although there is at least one case
that found a suspect was not free to leave, despite the warning8).
“You are free to leave”
Even though you're not handcuffed, would you feel like you could get up and walk out of an interrogation with a detective standing between you and the door? |
In
Howes v. Fields (2012)9,
the Court described the case of Randall Fields, an inmate in a Michigan jail.
Under suspicion of child abuse, Fields was interrogated one evening for 5 to 7
hours by armed sheriff’s deputies at the jail. The Court ruled that Fields was not
in custody despite the length of the interrogation, the fact that it occurred
after Fields usually went to sleep, the “very sharp tone” (p. 1193) of the
interrogators, and the fact that he was an inmate. Fields did not require
protections, according to the Court, because he was offered food and water, the
door to the interrogation room was not locked, and most importantly, he was
told that he was free to return to his jail cell whenever he desired.
With
this ruling, the Court expressed its confidence that telling a suspect he or
she is free to leave prevents feelings of restriction even in the face of
incarceration—the ultimate form of police custody. Twenty-two years before Howes, the U.S. Supreme Court similarly
held that an inmate being questioned by a police officer did not require Miranda warnings—not because the officer
told the inmate he was free to leave, but because the inmate did not know his
interrogator was a police officer.
The Perkins loophole
Illinois v. Perkins
(1990)10 presents one important exception to the custody inquiry.
Lloyd Perkins, an inmate in jail for aggravated battery, was in his cell when
two new cellmates arrived: (1) Donald Charlton, an inmate from another
correctional facility, and (2) John Parisi, an undercover police officer. Unbeknownst
to Perkins, Charlton and Parisi were working together to question Perkins about
an open murder case. The two undercover operatives engaged Perkins in a plan to
break out of the prison. If there was a shoot-out between prisoners and correctional
officers, Parisi needed to know if Perkins was willing to commit murder during
the break-out, and thus asked Perkins if he had ever killed before. Perkins
confirmed that he had and provided specific details of the murder after
prompting from both Parisi and Charlton. Perkins was subsequently arrested for
murder on the basis of his confession.
At
trial, Perkins’ statements were excluded from evidence because he was in
custodial interrogation without receiving or waiving Miranda. The U.S. Supreme Court reversed and allowed Perkins’
confession into evidence. The Court explained that Miranda warnings are only required because of the coercion that a
suspect might feel in a police-dominated setting. Although Perkins was
technically in custody as an inmate, the Court argued that he did not feel
coerced because he did not know his questioners were police agents.
Thus, Perkins limits Miranda to situations
in which the suspect knows the interrogator is a police officer. Opponents of
this decision, most notably Justice Thurgood Marshall in his dissent, argue
that in addition to being physically constrained by their incarceration,
inmates may feel psychologically restricted because prison is always a
police-dominated environment. Thus, inmates may have psychological
vulnerabilities that make them likely to boast about their (real or invented)
violent tendencies as a form of protection against prison violence, and in that
way feel pressured to make statements like Perkins’s. The Court’s decision in Perkins therefore denies safeguards to
one of the more vulnerable populations in need of the protection for which Miranda was created.
Interestingly, the Perkins Court specified that when determining whether the
questioning was coercive, courts must consider the perspective of the suspect. Regarding the more general
perception of freedom to leave, courts must use a different standard. The
objective circumstances described above are not to be considered from the
perspective of the suspect or the police present during the interrogation.
Instead, the courts ask how a reasonable
person would have interpreted those factors with regards to the suspect’s
freedom to leave.
Reasonable person
standard
Instead of asking police to weigh how each individual’s traits and idiosyncrasies might affect their perceptions of freedom, the courts ask whether a reasonable person would have felt restricted or free11. In other words, would the average person have felt free to get up and leave during the questioning? The assumption is that this reasonable person standard is more objective than the alternative12. Contrary to the law’s assumptions, psychological research shows that two “reasonable” people can perceive the same situation differently, depending on their perspective.
Instead of asking police to weigh how each individual’s traits and idiosyncrasies might affect their perceptions of freedom, the courts ask whether a reasonable person would have felt restricted or free11. In other words, would the average person have felt free to get up and leave during the questioning? The assumption is that this reasonable person standard is more objective than the alternative12. Contrary to the law’s assumptions, psychological research shows that two “reasonable” people can perceive the same situation differently, depending on their perspective.
Testing freedom to leave in the lab: People who watched a recording of the interrogation said the suspect was more free to leave than the suspect rated their own freedom to leave in the situation |
When
someone is in a bad situation, they report feeling less responsible and having
less freedom than when they are simply watching a bad situation. In contrast,
those watching from the outside report that the person in the situation had
more responsibility and freedom13. Timothy and I, along with Saul
Kassin, conducted two experimental studies to apply this difference in
perceptions of freedom to the custody test14. First, we wanted to
know whether the objective circumstances of a questioning session influence
subjects’ perceptions of custody. Second, we examined whether telling an
interview subject “you are free to leave” makes the subject feel freer than those
who are not told.
In
these studies, college student participants were questioned by campus security
about a staged theft that they believed to be real. The innocent participants
were either interviewed as witnesses to the crime or interrogated as suspects. The
interviews and interrogations questioning types consisted of objective factors
that would be considered noncustodial and custodial—and thus should elicit
greater feelings of freedom vs. restriction—respectively. Interviews were brief,
non-accusatory, information-gathering sessions, conducted with the door open
and with the experimenter in the room. Interrogations were longer, more
accusatory, and were conducted with the door closed and the participant alone
in the room with the security guard. All questioning sessions were
video-recorded. At the end of each session, participants reported how free they
felt to leave during the questioning.
Regardless
of questioning type, most participants did not feel free to leave. Contrary to
the law’s assumptions, participants did not feel freer in interviews vs.
interrogations—even when they were not accused and had an ally in the room,
participants felt a restriction on par with those in interrogations.
Next,
we examined whether telling someone they are free to leave during an interview
makes them feel more free to leave. In a similar fake theft scenario, we
randomly assigned some interview participants but not others to be informed of
their freedom. Participants who received the advisement knew objectively that
they were free to leave, but, contrary to the courts’ assumptions, did not feel freer compared to those who did not
receive the advisement.
In
both studies, we compared the participants’ perceptions of freedom to those of
neutral observers on the Internet. Although the laboratory participants felt
restricted, regardless of questioning type and advisement condition, online
observers did see a difference. Observers who watched an interview believed
that the subject was significantly freer to leave than those who watched an
interrogation; those who watched an interview with the advisement similarly
believed the subject was freer to leave than those with no advisement.
The
difference in perceptions between actors and observers closely mirrors the
results of previous psychological research12, showing that a
difference in perspective can influence attributions of freedom. The difference
between participants and observers also casts doubt on the objectivity of the
reasonable person standard by showing that two average, reasonable people can
draw different conclusions about custody based on their perspective.
In
addition to reporting their perceptions of the participant’s freedom, observers
were asked to put themselves in the participant’s position and report whether
they would feel free to leave in that situation. Interestingly, when observers
took the perspective of the participant, their perceptions of freedom dropped
significantly and closely matched the perceptions of the participants
themselves.
Taken
together, these two studies contradict the courts’ assumptions about: (1) how
objective circumstances (especially the free-to-leave advisement) influence perceptions
of custody and (2) the objectivity of the reasonable person standard. These
results raise the concern that freedom will be overattributed to suspects who
in fact feel restricted, and therefore they will not receive the legal
protections needed in custodial interrogation.
One
potential remedy also rises out of these results: an instruction to observers to
consider themselves in the suspect’s position while determining custody.
Indeed, Supreme Court Justices have recommended perspective-taking in this
manner (“…I have no doubt that the state trier of fact is best situated to put
himself in the suspect’s shoes, and consequently is in a better position to
determine what it would have been like for a reasonable man to be in the
suspect’s shoes”, p. 119)15. Custodial interrogation must be more
closely studied by psycho-legal scholars to prevent the curtailing of the only
two legal safeguards provided against self-incrimination—Miranda and video-recording.
References
1. Miranda v. Arizona, 384 US 436 (Supreme
Court 1966).
2. Orozco v. Texas, 394 US 324
(Supreme Court 1969).
3. California v. Beheler, 463 US
1121 (Supreme Court July 6, 1983).
4. US v. Griffin, 922 F. 2d 1343
(Court of Appeals, 8th Circuit 1990).
5.
US v. Brown, 990 F.2d 397 (8th Ci. 1993).
6. Oregon v. Mathiason, 429 US 492
(Supreme Court January 25, 1977).
7. Berkemer v. McCarty, 468 US 420
(Supreme Court July 2, 1984).
8. United
States v. Lee, 699 F.2d
466 (9th Cir. 1982).
9. Howes v. Fields, 132 S. Ct. 1181
(Supreme Court 2012).
10. Illinois
v. Perkins, 496 U.S.
292, 110 S. Ct. 2394, 110 L. Ed. 2d 243 (1990).
11. Stansbury v. California, 511 US
318 (Supreme Court April 26, 1994).
12. Yarborough v. Alvarado, 541 US
652 (Supreme Court 2004).
13. Harvey, J. H., Harris, B., &
Barnes, R. D. (1975). Actor-observer differences in the perceptions of
responsibility and freedom. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
32(1), 22–28. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0076852
14. Alceste, F., Luke, T. J. &
Kassin, S. M. (in press). Holding yourself captive: Perceptions of custody
during interviews and interrogations. Journal
of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jarmac.2018.03.001
15. Thompson v. Keohane, 516 US 99
(Supreme Court 1995).
These articles are exactly what I need. It is very nice of you to share your understanding. I have learned interesting things. I have a liking for your posts. Please, upload more and more posts. geometry dash , superhexio , pool 8 ball
ReplyDeleteI really loved reading your blog. It was very well authored and easy to undertand. Unlike additional blogs I have read which are really not tht good. I also found your posts very interesting. In fact after reading. I had to go show it to my friend and he ejoyed it as well!
ReplyDeleteminiclip games, a10 games to play, jogos para crianças
This blog was really great, never seen a great blog like this before. i think im gonna share this to my friends.. io jogos for kids
ReplyDeleteplay free 2 player game
friv free online juegos
ReplyDeletePokemon Magikarp Jump Online
Championship 2016
Hyper Vault
Hi to everybody, here everyone is sharing such knowledge, so it’s fastidious to see this site, and I used to visit this blog daily
The time needed for recuperation is determined dependent on the sort of crash and customer's prerequisites of information. We plan recuperation measure work-stream for each media submitted by the condition.recover-deleted-data.co.uk
ReplyDelete